58 pages • 1 hour read
A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Philosophy helps to recover a deeper meaning in our lives, which is sometimes hard to discern in everyday existence. It derives from the Greek word for “love of wisdom,” and it tackles the questions of existence that lie beyond the reach of science. Science informs the means of living, while philosophy informs the ends of life itself.
Philosophy includes logic, “the ideal method of thought”; aesthetics, “the study of ideal form” (i.e., beauty); ethics, “the study of ideal conduct”; politics, “the study of ideal social organization”; and metaphysics, “the study of the ‘ultimate reality of all things’” (4). There have been bad philosophers, but philosophy itself is a great good.
Of all ancient Greek city-states, Athens had the easiest access to the outside world, from which it acquired great wealth and knowledge of natural phenomena. Many of the same debates still shaping philosophic inquiry were formed in this day, such as the relationship of the individual to civilization.
Athens’s defeat against Sparta in the Peloponnesian War helped fuel a profound sense of skepticism toward the democratic government. The greatest philosopher of this time was Socrates, whose itinerant lifestyle and constant questioning of conventional wisdom won him a devoted following of students. His two principal questions, “what is the meaning of virtue? And what is the best state?” (13) provide the basis for political philosophy, by asking how good men could rule a good state and how good rule could produce good men. The Athenian democracy rejected Socrates’s teaching and ordered his execution for corrupting the youth, and so our knowledge of Socrates comes largely from the writings of his student Plato, who wrote many dialogues featuring Socrates and his students.
The most famous and comprehensive dialogue is the Republic, which begins with a discussion on the nature of justice. One participant, Thrasymachus, becomes impatient and insists that justice is nothing but the appeal of the weak against the strong, a claim later echoed by Nietzsche. Socrates admits the role of greed and power-seeking in political life, but that the ruler must look to the advantage of the ruled or else society itself will collapse. The ideal city must strike a balance between the different characters and appetites of its citizens, but this leaves the question of who has the power to set the balance. Socrates determines that knowledge is the key virtue for governance, and so the rulers of the city must be philosophers, the most knowledgeable members of the community.
Philosopher-kings will train children for lives of labor, military service, or—for a small handful—philosophical inquiry. Exercise will help reveal the extent of the child’s physical skill, while their reaction to musical education will provide the clearest indication of their emotional and psychological character. Regardless of their eventual station, all should learn to believe in a kind of god and immortal soul, so as to have “a personified ideal of our love and our hope” (35) as well as the courage to endure death if necessary, and the belief that their own social order is eternal because heaven ordains it.
For the eventual philosophers, the most important part of this education is the notion of “Ideas,” or idealized versions of all matter, which show that all of matter is part of a general pattern and therefore liable to study. The guardians, those trained for defense of the state, must hold all possessions (and their wives) in common, so that they learn to fight for the honor of the city rather than personal benefit. Private property will prevail among the artisans and laborers, but a contingent of guardians will watch over them to prevent any excessive concentrations of wealth. Plato’s contemplation of justice ends with its being “the having and doing what is one’s own” (47), where the needs and interests of all fit together with complete harmony.
Plato’s vision of society had a significant impact upon medieval Europe, where Catholicism taught fear of hell as a source of good conduct on earth, and a small class of hereditary warriors held unchallengeable power over the peasants and tradesmen. However, most of Plato’s readers find his plan impractical at best and monstrous at worst, with some arguing that it ignores basic facts of human nature and would destroy a community while trying to perfect it. For Durant, such critiques “destroy a straw man” (52), as Plato’s city left the majority alone while seeking to cultivate an elite.
Durant finds a stronger critique in Plato’s relative lack of attention to the relationship between politics and economic forces, which are far too dynamic for his static society to withstand. Utopias are meant to illustrate ideas, and do not necessarily need to demonstrate how to achieve them. Durant finds strong reasoning behind Plato’s central claim that the wisest should rule, and that this principle need not be irreconcilable with democracy.
This chapter establishes some of the themes that Durant will explore with each subsequent chapter, as part of his mission is to show how the great philosophers of the Western tradition are forever in dialogue with one another. He begins by placing Plato firmly within The Sociohistorical Context of Philosophy, showing that philosophy itself is not concomitant with civilization, but rather responds to circumstances that reverberate throughout the ages.
Durant regards the so-called “pre-Socratics” as not exactly philosophers in the modern sense of the word. In his estimation, they were interesting thinkers, but “they had sought for the physis or nature of external things, the laws and constituents of the material and measurable world” (12) whereas Socrates made the great innovation of turning to human beings as subjects of philosophic inquiry. It should be noted that Durant believes this to be a uniquely European innovation, and so he would presumably regard early non-Western thinkers as, at best, along the lines of the pre-Socratics.
Durant locates Socrates at the meeting point of a religious and political crisis, where natural philosophy had undermined faith in the gods and defeat in the Peloponnesian War undermined faith in democracy. With no remaining sources of traditional authority, human beings would have to look within themselves for knowledge. Socrates becomes the representative of this task both by virtue of his teachings (as we mostly know from Plato and Xenophon) and his way of life, where the pursuit of knowledge precluded work, attention to family, or any other conventional social institution. In one of the great ironies of history, Socrates is put to death by the authorities, only to establish himself posthumously as one of the great authorities of the Western intellectual tradition.
Plato’s Socratic dialogues further lay out the questions with which every single other member of the volume will have to contend. With the Republic providing the main source (with some references to the Laws, Gorgias, and a few others), a friendly conversation with an old and decidedly non-philosophic man on the nature of justice gradually expands into an entire imaginary city—a vehicle for a conversation on The Nature of Human Beings and Their World. Some philosophers will study the individual, and others the political unity, but for Plato the just city and the just individual are interconnected. Although Plato’s Socrates never explicitly defines justice in simple terms, it emerges as a balance of “desire, emotion, and knowledge” (29). In the city, the counterparts of these desires are the greedy average citizens (democracy), passionate soldiers (aristocracy), and wise leaders (monarchy), and while the latter must rule just as wisdom must govern the individual, all three elements must be present for a decent life and social existence. The objective is a life lived according to nature, but the difficulty with human beings is that their nature is not obviously manifest, and must be discovered through extensive trial and error. Only a relative handful of human beings will be capable of justice, according to Socrates, and so most human beings are consigned to living something less than a full human life.
Plus, gain access to 8,800+ more expert-written Study Guides.
Including features:
Appearance Versus Reality
View Collection
Beauty
View Collection
Community
View Collection
Good & Evil
View Collection
Inspiring Biographies
View Collection
Philosophy, Logic, & Ethics
View Collection
Psychology
View Collection
Science & Nature
View Collection
Trust & Doubt
View Collection
Truth & Lies
View Collection